floyd merrell

Purdue University

West Lafayette, IN  47907

 

 

THE “REAL,” WHAT WE (THINK WE) KNOW ABOUT IT,

AND SEMIOSIC BODYMIND FLOWS

 

MANY “REALITIES”

       From the Western perspective of the world, what, when, where, how, why, is the “real”?  These are all $64,000 dollar questions that are incessantly asked with obsessive curiosity.  Actually, in the ancient Christian tradition, we occasionally have the vague suggestion that we would be better off if we just remained ignorant.

       We first have the idea from the Old Testament.  There were two specially groomed trees in the Garden of Eden:  the Tree of Knowledge and the Tree of Life.  The story is common knowledge and I trust I need not recapitulate it here.   The point is that as a result of the original sin, the stage was set.  Knowledge, in the Christian tradition, brings riches and multiplies and pride and sin; therefore knowledge is bad.  Innocence cultivates poverty and humility, all of which are credentials for inheriting the Earth; therefore innocence is good.  The Faust legend created out of this myth has captivated writers like Johan Wolfgang von Goethe and Thomas Mann, among a host of others, and it has been played this idea to the hilt.

       But how can knowledge be bad if God possesses it in unlimited quantities?  Well, it isn’t bad.  At least it isn’t bad for God.  But it is for us sinners, because when we know, we become like God; we become aware of the difference between good and evil.  This should be good.  But it isn’t.  For there now exists the possibility of our doing evil knowingly instead of simply doing what we do in innocent bliss.  God doesn’t run this risk because s/he is immune from the Devil’s temptations.

       With the New Testament, irrationalism is added to the knowledge conundrum.  Christ is both God and human.  He is God, because he was immaculately conceived, and he is man, for, after all, he could in the most ungodly way suffer crucifixion and death.  To make matters worse, we have the Holy Trinity as three fused into one and one subdivided into three in simultaneity.  Following Roman philosopher Tertullian, the whole scheme is inconceivable, logically impossible, nonsensical, and meaningless.  So the only recourse is to accept it on faith.  And faith it was, in contrast to reason.  The unsavory contention between the two extremes got the West out of the starting blocks and onto the long road toward ever increasing knowledge, secular knowledge, in its eternal conflict with religion and faith. 

       In the beginning, Greek philosophers grappled intensively with this problem.  Some of them even thought they got it right.  But there was always a little contradiction or a few paradoxes lurking around in the shadows.  During the Medieval period and afterward, the Church was supposed to have all the answers, and many a life was lost due to heretical deviations from the one-and-only “truth.”  A few philosophers, in spite of the warning signs, continued their quest for their own “truths,” and they ran many risks on so doing.  With the Renaissance came Western science in the pursuit of the “truth” regarding natural phenomena.  Nothing but more heresy, as far as the Church was concerned.  But now it had trouble coping with science’s success.  Science was also cutting into what philosophers considered to be their exclusive turf.  The ensuing miscommunication and resentment and bickering went on for over three centuries.  Then science made bold moves into life and its origin, and there were even incursions into human affairs.  The hold Church fathers and philosophers enjoyed over souls and minds suffered another set back.

       Finally, as a last resort, during the heyday of a philosophical movement called empirical positivism, philosophers either began telling the scientists what they were doing, where they had gone wrong, and where they should go in the future, or they gravitated into areas of human concerns:  values, ethics aesthetics, and such.  Science, with the labels “social” and “human,” began laying bare this last stand of virgin territory.  Outcries of “secular humanism,” “alienation,” and other somber warnings filled the air.  It seemed that philosophers now had nowhere else to go.  So they retreated into texts and discourse and narratives and language.  And religion became a one-day-a-week affair at most.  Science, that new chant venerating the ultimate triumph of culture over nature by mind, was now having its day.

       In short, many questions were posed and many answers given.  But the fundamental questions remained.  These questions surfaced with a vengeance during the twentieth century.  It appeared to some onlookers that all hell had broken loose.  Occasional doomsayers declared that absolute certainty had become a pipe dream, and the idea of complete and consistent knowledge had gone the way either of phlogiston or the alchemy.  As if this were not enough, the death knell to tired minds wanting irrefutable answers came at the hands of physicists, of all people.  Physics:  that prince of the sciences, that to which in the heyday of logical positivism presumably all other sciences could be reduced, that reputed source of answers to end all answers.  Gone were the days when physics could be evoked as the grand authoritarian voice.  Now, take a handful of Nobel laureates of that noble science and you may find just as many interpretations of the world.  Each physicist may have his alternate interpretation of what goes by the umbrella term, “reality,” and all of them may engage in no-holds-barred competition for acceptance of their newest theories.  There is the sneaky feeling that “truth,” the “whole truth and nothing but the truth,” is beyond reach, and that “reality” is unattainable.

       “Reality,” one might now be prone to conclude, is a smorgasbord of theories and conjectures, a salad bar of words and worlds.  It can be fast food gulped down in the form of the pop physics that abounds these days.  It can be the soul food of Zen physics, or a new age vegetarian diet of “the real is us” so let’s feel good about ourselves and be happy.  It can be a sushi theory of raw sensations is all we have and so that’s all we need.  It can be meat and potatoes materialism in the order of what you see is what there is.  It can be dessert bar ego-feeding time to the tune of “reality” is what our consciousness makes it.  Or it can all be wrapped up in that confusing variety of conflicting side-dish interpretations with apparently no resolution in sight that goes by the name of quantum theory (Goswami 1993, Herbert 1985).

       But things did not always appear so hopeless.  Up until the end of the present century, optimism most often reigned.  Given the mind-boggling diversity the world presents to the confused onlooker, a set of fundamental premises was established prior to and during much of the seventeenth century and the Baroque period—itself a paragon of pluralism—for the purpose of laying conflicts regarding “reality” to rest for all time.  Over the years, this set of premises became entrenched in the minds of us Westerners to the extent that they now color our world, the world we live in.  However strange and even inconsistent these premises might have seemed in the beginning, they eventually come to appear as natural as could be.  They coincided with the world according to what became conceived as the most commonsensical of assumptions.  And what were these premises?  They came in large part from René Descartes in the form of mind/world and mind/body severances.  These were largely metaphysical premises, rather than scientific premises.  They were the result of the philosopher’s wish to be a geometer and scientist.  Descartes by and large fulfilled his wish and in the process produced some philosophy so convincing that it exercised a remarkable degree of intellectual dominance since his time.

Other premises came from the beginnings of modern science:  Galileo Galilei’s grand division between the hard-core exact and measurable empirical world in contrast to the appearances handed down by the qualities of the mind’s subjective nature.  Successive scientists took Galileo’s project to its most sublime end, especially Isaac Newton, who set the foundations for the emergent mechanical model of the universe.  Newton’s theory was presumably of purely scientific, that is, of inductive, nature, and hypothetico-deductive hypotheses as if drawn from a vacuum were considered anathema.  What went as purely inductive premises were the product of scientists who wished to remain lily clean of all metaphysical blemishes but who, in spite of themselves, allowed a few hypothetical assumptions to creep in.[1]

 

THE GREAT BIFURCATION

       To make another long story short, the Galilean-Cartesian-Newtonian corpuscular-kinetic notion of the world entails, as Descartes himself portrayed it, an external world made up exclusively of res extensa (physical- or extended-stuff) chock full of subjective experience consisting of mushy, and imprecise sensations such as color, tone, odor, taste, and touch.  All those qualities are considered scientifically unimportant.  They are mere “secondary qualities,” a matter of the subject’s grasp of his world according to his emotions, sentiments, and whims and fancies.  As such, they are of the world of appearances and not what is “real” in the most legitimate sense.

The genuine nature of the “real” is of utmost importance.  It is available solely by way of res cogitans (mind-stuff).  The world of res extensa, as the object of res cogitans, becomes Descartes’s genuine focus of thought rather than subjective appearances, sentiment, emotions.  Res cogitans, when on its best behavior, is capable of telling us what is “real,” the “reality” of “primary qualities,” rather than the imaginary, illusory, deceptive, magical and mythical reports given up by the subjective mind attending to “secondary qualities.”  And how does res cogitans manage accomplish this trick?  Not by attending to subjectively received colors and sounds and smells and tastes and touches, but by measuring and calibrating and computing the word objectively, and giving it mathematical rather than merely linguistic window dressing.  According to the epistemological giants of the day, hard-nosed “macho thinking” eventually became the arena of res cogitans, while all those other trivial, soft mental pursuits purportedly became the fickle ways of “women’s thinking.”

This, of course, is putting things in possibly misleading and dangerous terms—to say nothing of their “political incorrectness.”  But once again, we can pretty much wrap up the history of Western thought and science according to these two Cartesian categories.  Consequently, in Alfred North Whitehead’s (1925) words, “misplaced concreteness” had its say, and the grand “bifurcation of nature” took precedence over any and all alternative ways of finding a home in the universe.

       Admittedly, the grand Cartesian dichotomy in certain ways came in quite handy.  By a stroke of the pen, tender “secondary” mind was sent off to do an internship in primary school under the tutelage of the local nuns, while tough, no nonsense “primary” mind went to an academy that would prepare him for a solid degree in mathematics at the Venerable Institute of Technology.  In this manner the task before the scientist was incalculably simplified.  The world of res extensa accounted for by res cogitans fell conveniently into the hands of those who happened to be mathematically endowed.  According to the most optimistic reports, the entire universe could in principle be comprehended, mathematically comprehended that is, which was considered the only comprehension worthy of the name.  All the other less mathematically minded folks would have to remain content with their exceedingly impoverished poetic accounts, and leave the intellectual rigors to their more capable counterparts.

Plato once banished the poets from the circle of hard core thinkers.  Now all citizens of the world, save a few adult men with the proper tools, would have to take on authority what was handed down to them by the number gurus.  And authority it was, in spite of Descartes’s antiauthoritarian “I” of “I think.”  For, that “I” was a most privileged “I.”  It was certainly not available to just anybody.  The Cartesian “I” saw a “reality” made up of things that have measurable attributes:  mass, momentum, position in space, continuous existence in time expressed as inertia, energy taken in or expended.  “Reality” was considered reducible to just that, and it was so reduced insofar as reductionism was possible.

Eventually, the entire project triumphed beyond the wildest of imaginations.  It is hard to argue with such success.  In fact, the objective, mechanistic view was so successful, and it became so taken for granted, that any viable alternative seemed well nigh impossible.  After some 300 years of accomplishments, scientists, philosophers, scholars of all disciplines, and indeed, virtually all knowledgeable citizens of the Western World, were either in a state of euphoria, in a drunken stupor over their intoxication with their unexpected prosperity, or with a hangover and a head full of cobwebs.  Few onlookers heeded the dark clouds that raised their ominous countenance in the distant horizon.[2]

       However, there was a price to be paid for privileging Descartes’s res cogitans (mind-stuff) over res extensa (matter-stuff).  Once the world had been bifurcated and given a linear, digital, analytic, mathematical account, nobody apparently knew how to put the pieces back together again into a whole, the whole universe, that contained both res extensa and res cogitans as well as body and mind (or better, bodymind) of “secondary qualities” and mindbody of “primary qualities.”  For example, how do we know our world?  Why, by the senses, of course.  But what is it that we sense?  One might wish to respond that we sense what there is.  This was pretty much the commonsensical assumption before the advent of modern science.  It was generally taken for granted that philosophers and common people alike all sense the world “out there” in pretty much the same way.

Not so, said the early scientists, beginning with Galileo and culminating with Descartes.  If one accepts the “bifurcation of nature” premise, one must conclude that when one perceives a “red” apple, the apple’s color is no more than mere subjectivity.  The apple’s genuine attributes belong to the objectively oriented side of res cogitans and res cogitans alone.  This is a matter of “primary qualities,” that which can be accurately measured and given clear and distinct mathematical window-dressing.  The color of the apple one sees when expressed in terms of “primary qualities,” so the story goes, is no more than a combination of light rays with certain wave-lengths and their particular frequencies.  This is “macho” knowledge, liberated from its dependency on mere appearances.

The mushy, error-prone subjective self senses “secondary qualities.”  This is all right as far as our sentiments and passions and wishes and whims and likes and dislikes go.  “Secondary qualities” are the colors and sounds and smells and tastes and tactile sensations of our world.  But they do not lead us to hard-core knowledge of what there is, says the “macho” scientist.  “Secondary qualities” are not part of res extensa as it really stands, for pure res extensa in the objective sense will have nothing to do with the subjective side of mind; it has no use for “secondary qualities.”

Res extensa, then, is actually no more than so many juxtaposed wave lengths each of a certain frequency, so many areas of compacted and diffuse air pockets, so many stimulated nerve endings on the mucous membrane area of the nose or at the tip of the tongue or on  the surface of the skin.  Thus what is sensed is sensed in a private, subjective world.  It is not what is “real” at all.  In this subjective sense of sensing the world, neither scientist nor nonscientist is clearly and distinctly in tune with the world.  Both are imprisoned within their own private worlds.  What they subjectively take for their “real world” is a ghost world.  It is like a dream, whose existence does not extend beyond what their senses directly tell them.  These direct sensations, loose and imprecise, are good for gazing at art or a sunset, for listening to music or warbling birds, for enjoying the aroma and taste of fine food and drink, for reading poetry, and for making love in the dark.  But they give us no solid knowledge about the world.

       However, problems with this conception of things eventually arose.  With respect to what Whitehead considered the grand Cartesian “bifurcation of the world,” consider this.  On the one hand, if we directly sense the world in terms of “secondary qualities,” and if what is genuinely “real” is  the world of “primary qualities” that are not directly sensed but the product of scientific measurements, then how can “primary qualities” be known if there is no form or fashion of direct sensation of the “secondary qualities” sort?  Must “secondary qualities” not enter the scene when the scientist is handling the tools of her trade and reading instruments and tapping at the computer terminal and making observations in natural environments?  On the other hand, if “primary qualities” are at some point brought to the mind’s attention by way of “secondary qualities,” then how can the one “world” be “real” and the other “irreal”?  If “secondary qualities” are “irreal,” then the information they hand up to the scientist in pursuit of “primary qualities” when she is engaged in the concrete affairs of her experimental procedures must be equally “irreal.”  So at what point do these “secondary qualities” magically enter the “real” within the ethereal zone of “primary qualities”?  It would seem that both “primary” and “secondary” considerations of the “world” are bound up in Descartes’s mind, or better, bodymind.

       With this problem in hand, I hope to illustrate in the following pages that body and brain tell mind (or better, bodymind) what “secondary qualities” what we sense in the “world.”  Consequently mind cannot sense “primary qualities” as measured and quantified data in the “world” without body and brain.  But when confronting this problem, we find ourselves caught up in a dilemma.  Descartes created a virtually unbridgeable gap between “secondary qualities” and “primary qualities,” res extensa and res cogitans.  If in the Cartesian sense sensations cannot bridge the abyss between res cogitans and res extensa, then how is it possible to bridge the abyss at all?  How is it possible genuinely to know the world?  Or even know that a world “out there” exists in the first place?

As far as my seriously limited understanding goes, Descartes himself had lingering doubts in this regard.  In his effort to come to grips with his doubts, he left a tortuous argument.  In spite of its difficulty, the argument sports a few naïve assumptions that few scholars would care to take at face value in light of today’s world of avant garde art over the past century, and of relativity and quantum physics, chaos theory, virtual reality, and global pluralism of cultures.  Yet the Cartesian impasse remains.  It often takes the form of what Richard Bernstein (1983) dubs “Cartesian anxiety” (either we become enlightened, or we will fall victims to the dark, devilish depths of superstition and false beliefs and ignorance).  Granted.  After the grand bifurcation, mathematization of the world seemed to hold unlimited promise.  But is the great mathematical cut worth tossing everything else into the trash can?  Especially when that “everything else” includes gazing at the sunset, listening to a Bach fugue, smelling honeysuckle blossoms, eating an exquisite plate of pasta, and making love?  When that “everything else” is what makes life worth living after all is said and done?

       In a certain manner of putting it, only by a strange sort of move did “Cartesian anxiety” fall in step with that age-old split between the two grand schools of Western thought:  idealism and realism.  In a nutshell, idealism says everything consists of mind-stuff; realism counters that the world consists of real, actualized physical-stuff.  For Descartes, mind-stuff (res cogitans) takes priority over physical-stuff (res extensa), for it is what can be known by objective methods of measurement and calculation.  Hence mind can get in tune with and mirror the world.  For the naïve sort of realist, what you know is what you see and what you see is what there is, so in the best possible scenario what is in mind mirrors what is “out there.”  This would seem to imply that Cartesianism inclines toward idealism.  But not exactly.  Mind must act on the world objectively in order to generate its mind-stuff.  It does not simply sit around and wait for something interesting to happen.  At the same time, whatever genuine information mind squeezes out of the world consists of “primary qualities,” which are available to mind and mind alone.  Mind is by no means a passive recipient of physical-stuff.

       In contrast to the Cartesian program, the story I tell in the inquiry entails both body and mind (bodymind) as sign (bodymindsign).  Both body and mind are co-participants in the process of their becoming in concert with the becoming of their world.  This is a sort of middle path between idealism and realism, or in Bernstein’s (1983) words, between “objectivism and relativism.”  It is neither idealism nor realism, neither subjectivism nor objectivism, neither relativism nor antirelativism but, as we shall note, much in the order of what Peirce called “objective idealism.”[3]  So much for the Cartesian quandary.

       For the next move, please allow me simply to try stating my piece outright.  Then perhaps I can get on with it:

 

(1)    There is a world, somehow, and it is “real.”

(2)    No more than a part of the world (The World) can be included in what we call “our world,” for we can never know the “real” in its entirety.  Our minds are too feeble and fallible and the world is too complex and subtle.

(3)    We are not as limited as the first two premises might suggest, for at every step we make of “our world” something other than what it was becoming, and we possess the potentiality for making it in the future something other than what it is now becoming.

“Our world” is “our world,” for sure.  It is what it is, “for us,” and we are what we are “for it,” at least for the moment, since the next moment will present something other than what the present moment presents.

The notions of “for us” and “for it” are tough nuts to crack, however, and the best I can hope for in this very modest meditation on living semiosis is to display the meaning of the terms throughout the story I have to tell.  For now, perhaps the most I can say is this:  we sense “our world” and we never cease our attempts to say it, but we cannot really say it, for what we sense is more than can be said.  Moreover, much of what we sense we know—”tacit knowledge” via Michael Polanyi (1958, see also Margolis 1993)—and part of what we sense and know is part of what we cannot say, so we know more than we can say.  In this manner it is futile to speak of a split between what is “real” and what is fantasy, between what is “in here” and what is “out there,” between what we can see and say and what we cannot see and say, and between what can be known and what cannot be known.[4]

       Now what I have written to this point is an eyeful and you are most likely asking...

 

SO, WHERE DO WE NEED TO GO, WHERE CAN WE GO?

       Where do we need to go, after the shortcomings of the Galileo-Cartesian-Newtonian corpuscular-kinetic view of the “real” have become painfully apparent?  Another $64,000 question.  However, please don’t expect any ultimate answers from me.  For centuries, minds infinitely more competent than mine have tried and failed.

       Nevertheless, I would at least venture to suggest:  a turn to our role as co-participants with rather than actors on the world, and the interdependent, interrelated, interactivity with respect to ourselves and our world.  In the twentieth century, this turn was initiated from many angles.  To mention a few instances revealing this turn, it is found in certain interpretations of quantum theory (Herbert 1985).  We sense it in ecology and John Lovelock’s (1979) Gaia hypothesis.  There is a hint of the idea in Mikhail Bakhtin’s literary theory and in certain strains of what go by the names of “poststructuralism” and “deconstruction” and “postmodernism” (Emerson 1997).  We occasionally run into it in feminist, gay, cultural and ethnic studies (Bordo 1987, Haraway 1991).  We read about it in recent philosophy, history, sociology, and anthropology of science (Barnes, et al. 1996, Fuller 1993, Koertge 1998).  It is often implied in recent chaos theory  (Gleick 1987).  It is crucial to an understanding of Ilya Prigogine’s physics of complexity (Prigogine and Stengers 1983).  We even find smatterings of it in New Age ramblings and in other popular trends.  But actually, this idea is nothing new at all.  Over the centuries, it has popped up in Western thought along the lines of the Heraclitean tradition.  And, of course, it is central to much Eastern thought.

       My own inclinations along these lines would initially evoke the name of North American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce.  Why Peirce?  Because he most emphatically stressed the importance of the entire community of knowers over the idea of self-serving, self-promoting, ego-driven individualism, that has become rampant in our contemporary global scene and especially in the West.  Because he nurtured a belief in the importance of open dialogue between humans and humans, humans and other living creatures, and humans and nature at large.  Because he obstinately refused to buy into the heralded mind/body, subject/object, culture/nature, and human/nonhuman, splits, while maintaining that dichotomies of thought are actually matters of degree rather than kind.  Because he believed signs pervade the entire universe and that we as well as all organisms are signs among signs and that signs grow much in the order of organic growth.  Because he had a profound respect for nature and the whole of the universe.  Finally, because I sense that Peirce may have much to offer those of us who are seeking answers to overwhelmingly complex aesthetic, ethical, and moral issues with which we are confronted in our contemporary milieu.

       But this is neither the time nor the place to get heavy with Peirce’s thought.  Let’s get on with bodymind and its wordl.[5]

 

ON WHAT WE THINK THE WORLD WE MADE IS?

       How is the world ordinarily described in the scientific mold?  By timeless, mechanical equations rendering “primary qualities” intelligible?  No, not really.  Nevertheless, the common assumption usually has it that equations of the F = MA sort are entirely objective, and applicable in exactly the same way everywhere and everywhen.  In classical physics, however, the world is described mathematically in terms of differential equations.  These equations, of the calculus, involve change over time.  The equation, dx/dt gives us a linear stream of “differentials” regarding something, x, that changes in time, t.

“Differentials” are just that, differentials or minute, infinitesimally minute, differences that something undergoes during a certain increment of time.  In more recent mathematics we have fractal geometry, the patterns of which come to full bloom as the same algorithm is repeated, over and over again, potentially to infinity, the “over and over again” taking up time.  Time must come into the picture, for if not, nothing can be described.  Whatever there is, x, changes in time, t, in virtually infinitesimally minuscule increments in equally minuscule increments of time.  Everything is always becoming something other than what it was becoming.  Your car is becoming somewhat less than precisely honed pistons and valves and crankshaft and camshaft alternator wheel.  It is frayed upholstery becoming, deteriorated rubber packing becoming, worn tire becoming, marred window becoming, sun-blistered plastic becoming, rusted body becoming, perforated muffler becoming.[6]

       After life as a child and a young man in the Southwestern part of the United States, and after finishing my PhD work at the University of New Mexico in May of 1973, I bought a slightly used VW camper van and, with wife and three offspring, we traveled to San Francisco and down the coast and to Mexico City to visit my wife’s family.  Before we knew it, it was August.  So we headed up to Albuquerque, filled a rental truck and hauled East to West Lafayette, Indiana and Purdue University, where my first and only academic job was waiting.   I knew little of the climate in the “Heartland of America,” and assumed the trusty VW van would last a lifetime.  To my surprise, the van turned rusty within a mere couple of years.  Weatherproofing was virtually nonexistent in the Southwest, and I thought I had no need of putting a coat it on a now four-year old vehicle in Indiana.

Or at least so I thought.  The van became very shortly the repository of irreversible rust becoming.  In response, I would periodically grind off the rust with a skimpy ¼ inch drill fixed with a sander attachment, plug the holes with liberal gobs of body putty, sand them down, put on some primer, and paint over them with an aerosol can of paint from the department store (the van was white, and, after all, white is white, isn’t it?).  It was a hopeless struggle.  Eventually I gave up and allowed nature to take its course, and ended up in 1991 selling my van for a song.  Rust becoming was destined to win in the end.  Time eventually reaps its harvest from everything and everybody.  I had learned a lesson on the impermanence of all things and about my ego-centered tendency to become attached to inanimate material things.  Like my van’s rust becoming, I repeat, everything is becoming something other than what it was becoming.

       But we still nurture a natural tendency to balk.  Efficiently inculcated in our Western science-driven ways, our mind persists, and indeed it often excels, in the ability to treat its world as if there were nothing new under the sun, as if there were really nothing that is entirely strange.  Consequently, we persist in our mule-headed insistence on interpreting what is different in our world in terms of what we already thought we knew.  This is often preferable when our tender egos are taken into account.  It gives us the security that what we think we know is all we need to know, as far as our world goes, and there’s no sense in going further than that.  We prefer this security rather than attend to, and marvel at, during each moment, what our feelings and sensations tell us about our world’s incessant becoming.  To admit to this becoming, one would expect, is surely to fall into confusion and chaos—i.e. “Cartesian anxiety.”

       Eastern sages also tell us that (1) all things are impermanent.  They teach us that (2) nobody has an ego unless the ego is constructed by artificial means, that (3) what we find ourselves doing at each and every moment we should do as if it were of ultimate importance no matter how mundane it might appear, and that (4) the ultimate in knowing is quietude, solitude, silence, nothingness, “emptiness.”  Let’s briefly take these four principles one by one.  We might wish to construe “all things are impermanent” to mean that all that exists must eventually die or decay and fade into oblivion.  This is the negative interpretation.  There is another way of looking at the phrase.  In a genuine—though not necessarily a positive—sense, although neither nothing nor nobody is fixed, permanent, or immortal, after decay there is renewal, after destruction there is reconstruction, after life there is birth.  In this sense the idea of impermanence is valueless, neutral.  There is no positive and negative, good side and bad side, there is just impermanence, period.  It is just change, incessant change wherein everything is becoming something other than what it was becoming.  That’s all.

Express the change of velocity of a vehicle when it accelerates from 0 to 70 miles per hour, and slap it all on the Cartesian plane by means of analytic geometry, and you have the change.  It’s all there, timelessly, for all to see, as a set of “primary qualities.”  It’s change, for sure.  But it’s by and large valueless.  Where is the exhilaration you experience when putting the car in gear and stomping on the gas pedal as you let up on the clutch and feeling your head try to flip back and detach itself from a few vertebrae?  Where is the tingling sensation in your guts as your torso is pressed against the back of the seat?  In other words, where are the “secondary qualities”?  Within the abstract Cartesian plane, there are no eyes catching a glimpse of the speedometer in anticipation of a needle rapidly moving from left to right.  There is just a bunch of symbols and a few lines on a flat sheet of paper.  That’s all.  There’s just change expressed through gutless abstractions.  Which brings up the second, third, and fourth principles in the above paragraph:  if you and your euphoric feeling inside the accelerating automobile are not part of the neutral change, the becoming of the becoming, then there is no ego, not really.  If there is no ego, and if everything is just there, then there are no values, no good or evil, and no genuine opposites.  If there are no ultimate values, then what could be more important than what is happening at each moment of our lives, whether we are driving down the street or walking up a stairway, getting dressed or undressed, eating or cleaning up the table, gazing at a sunset or watching CNN news, or taking an exam or closing a business deal.  If this is the case, then no moment is any more important than complete quietude, solitude, silence, nothingness, “emptiness.”  That’s all.

       We naturally renege.  We want things that are important to us to stand out.  We want them to be replete with meaning, significance, value.  We want this meaning, significance, value, to be articulable and articulated in language.  Thus we are accustomed to saying things as if we were to say “This means that.”  But rarely do we pause to reflect on this strange linguistic structure.  Is it really possible that there can something we call “this”?  Is it possible that “this” could refer to, correspond to, represent, or in any form or fashion present a mirror image of, “that”?  Could the word connected to some “this” actually mean something else, “that”?  If so, in what way, if at all, is it like “that”?  Is there a correspondence between words and things, words and meanings?  We customarily take things not as what they are but in terms of something similar that we happened to find in some corner of our memory.  And we conveniently make the connection.  We’ve grown quite comfortable with our laziness, or at least with our inability to take things in our accustomed manner for what they are outside their interdependency, interrelatedness, and interaction with other things.  We don’t take them as they would appear prior to our so integrating them, prior to our conceptualizing them and generalizing them and throwing them into our convenient pigeon-holes.  But we are deluding ourselves.  Allow me to offer another story.

       Some time ago when in Brazil for the first time and struggling with the Portuguese language, I found myself in the market place.  Spying some strange fruit—at least I took it for a member of the things that I usually gave the “fruit” label—I asked the vendor what these quaint items were.  I was told “maracujá.”  To that I simply gave the mindless response:  “Obrigado” (“Thanks”).  I didn’t ask her to explain what “maracujá” was or what it was like, since given my frail knowledge of the language I probably wouldn’t have understood her anyway.  I heard the word as if it referred to that strange “fruit” before me and as if it corresponded to some meaning.  I simply took the word at face value, and walked off as if I knew what she had told me in response to my question and as if I had learned a valuable piece of information.  But I didn’t, and I hadn’t.  What had I actually learned?  I really knew no more than I did a few seconds previous to the encounter except that those strange looking things were given the nonsensical set of syllables “ma-ra-cu-já.”  If the person in the next stall had happened to have asked me if I knew what his specimens of the same fruit were, I would have naturally nodded my head and made a sound roughly the equivalent of “ma-ra-cu-já.”  I would also have had little idea what I was talking about.  We have the tendency to think that when we know a name, we know what something in our word is.

       I had not taken the time to try interrelating “maracujá” with things with which I was familiar in order to expand my understanding of the object before me.  Had I done so, I might have come up with “passion fruit” in English, and I would have been right.  “Maracujá” is “passion fruit.”  Well and good.  But what do I now know?  I know that there is a word in English, “passion fruit” that we use in somewhat the same way as the people in Brazil use when speaking Portuguese and they utter the sound “maracujá.”  What valuable bit of knowledge does that afford me?  Not much, really.  The pair of words tells me very little about what we call “reality.”  It says little regarding the “reality” of appearances, of “secondary qualities,” and it says nothing at all with respect to the “reality” of “primary qualities.”

In order to learn something, we have to value the words, give them meaning.  Initiator of modern linguistics, Ferdinand de Saussure (1966), often used the word “value” in much the same way we use “meaning.”  Words have value, value given them by their users, and if they have value they have meaning.  But according to Saussure, the values we attach to words is a matter of the interdependent, interactive, interrelations between each word and all the other words in a language.  What the value of a given word would be outside any and all other words nobody knows.  What value “maracujá” or “passion fruit” would have in isolation from all words in Portuguese or English respectively is your guess as well as mine, if value there could be at all.

       Up to this point Saussure was pretty much on track.  All words are interdependent, interrelated, and interactive with all other words.  The same can be said of the objects, acts, and events in our “world.”  This being the case, if the context changes, ever so slightly, then the use of a particular word within that context will change, and every word in the entire repertoire within the head of a given speaker will undergo a change, however slight.  I am told that the thing before me is “maracujá.”  Now I know.  But I don’t really know much of anything that I didn’t know before.  Yet I know that this particular item right here, along with its immediate neighbors in this stall, carry the same name.  And the same goes for similar items in the next stall, and the next, today, yesterday, and tomorrow.  So I know a little more, and I have begun generalizing the word.  Then I learn that “maracujá” in Portuguese is “passion fruit” in English.  Now I have integrated the word in one language with a word in my home language.  So I know a little more.  But very little more.

       How can I know more?  In order to enhance my own personal knowledge, knowledge by way of “secondary qualities,” knowledge that creates my concrete, everyday bodymind world of experience, I must handle the fruit, open it and gaze at its visible properties, smell it, and taste it, over and over again if I find it to my liking—which I most certainly do.  I must make up part of my life’s experience as of one year, two years, three years, and many years in the past.  A chemical qualitative and quantitative analysis of its ingredients won’t be of much value in this regard.  What is important is concrete experience, in the past, at present, and in the future.  These experiences will be the same, yet context mandates that each experience will be somewhat new.  The fruit will always be the same fruit, whether I label it “maracujá” or “passion fruit.”  At the same time, it will be different.

 

WHY WE SHOULD BE AWARE THAT THE WORLD WE MADE IS BECOMING

       There is a paradox in the preceding section with respect to knowledge.  If I think I know a little more by learning what something is in terms of its respective name, and if I have learned that little bit more through a mapping of what it is in one language onto what it is in another language, then I have learned something about what I presume it is, was, and will be.  Moreover, I feel comfortable that I will be able to apply the same sort of knowledge to all like things I might have come across in the past, what might happen to be in my particular vicinity now, and what I might happen to run into in the future, till the day I croak.

In other words, with respect to a particular specimen of a general class of things called “maracujá” or “passion fruit,” if I wish, I can see it right here, now, in my imagination.  It is one thing and one thing only.  Yet with respect to its label, “maracujá” or “passion fruit,” it is many things.  At the same time, it is what it is, no more, no less, here and now.  Yet yesterday it was something other than what it is here and now.  It was plumper, of slightly different color, and it didn’t have as many of those minuscule insects flying around it.  Besides that, if it doesn’t finds its way into some customer’s shopping bag, within a couple of more days it will likely be unfit for consumption, since it is about as impermanent as fruit comes.  So the object in question is not one and it is one, but it is also many, not one.  And it is not identical to itself over time.  If we wish to hold the world in our conceptual framework consisting of static categories of thought, it lithely slithers beyond our grasp; and if we want to know its impermanence, then forget about fixed categories altogether.

       This conundrum has in philosophical circles since the time of the Greeks been known as the Paradox of One and Many—or of the Particular and the General.  One variation of the paradox is that of the heap.  Make a pile of sand on the beach and call it a “heap.”  It is many like things that are given a definite label and that label only.  Now remove ten grains.  Is it still a heap?  Of course it is!  Remove ten more grains, and continue the algorithm over and over again.  After precisely which of the algorithmic moves can you confidently say the heap of no longer a heap?  A problem.  Reconsider my VW van.  When I bought it there was no visible rust.  I should know.  As a fresh Ph.D. with little money in my pocket I went over it with a fine-tooth comb.  After two years, there was some rust.  Was it the same van?  I would like to think so.  Two more years, and you guessed it.  The same van?  Yes.  Two years later, then two added to the two, over and over again.  Did it remain the one I once purchased?  Of course, it was my van and nobody else’s, damnit!—though, for sure, I was no longer as proud of it as I once was.  From one angle, it was one:  mine and mine alone.  From another angle, it was, at each and every moment, in the process of becoming something other than what it was becoming:  it was many.

A host philosophical problems in Western thought has been caught up in the One-Many Paradox.  To mention a few, mind/body (body is subject to the ravages of time, while mind remains imperiously immune to the body’s deterioration); free will/determinism (am I free?, of course I am, I can do whatever I want at this particular moment, for given my existence as Many, each moment is a bifurcation into one direction or the other and I am free to choose, but am I free when considering the entirety of my life?, no, not if I am considered One); subject/object (the first is One, the second Many, according to circumstances); nature/nurture (the first is One, the second is Many, according to environment); absolute/relative (the first is One, the second is Many, depending on context).  And so on.

We also find the One and the Many in the wave/particle complementarity of quantum theory.  The wave interpretation of quantum theory is One.  When the “wave packet” undergoes a collapses into a particle-happening, it is Many.  To the question is the quantum world of wave nature, the answer is “Yes and no”; to the question is it of particle nature, the answer is “Yes and no”; to the question is it both of wave nature and particle nature the answer is “Yes and no,” to the question is it neither of wave nature nor particle nature, the answer is “Yes and no.”  So where are we, anyway?  In good keeping with the One-Many Paradox, we are everywhere and nowhere, both right and wrong and neither right nor wrong.

Intriguing, puzzling, and perhaps more than a little disconcerting.

 

ON WHAT ISN’T:  THE ONLY CONSTANT?

       So, let us ask a variation of the question we posed above.  How should the world, and our relationship with the world, be described?  By talking, for sure, since it is the best means we have for communicating, however flawed it may be.  At the same time, we must keep in mind that all things are impermanent, that nobody actually has an ego worthy of the name, that what we find ourselves doing at each and every moment is of ultimate importance, that there are no values, no good or evil, no opposites, and that in the final analysis here is only quietude, solitude, silence, nothingness, or better put, “emptiness.”  Everything is flow, and behind the flow there is only “emptiness.”  Today’s ecologists give us a lot of cryptic and apocalyptic and statistical talk.  Yet one of the common words that continues to surface time and time again is flow.

       Flow.  What it tells us is that everything is already becoming something other than what it is becoming.  It tells us that if we forget our lives and our world are incessant process, and if we go along stubbornly assuming we can exercise control over the whole process, then we’re in for a big surprise.  We are bound to pay the consequences in the long run.  In other words, we tend to impose our embedded, entrenched, preconceived and quite flawed conceptual categories of thought (Generalities) on the world (of Particulars) as if it were one thing composed of a set of fixed things, and we ignore the manyness and the impermanence of all that is becoming.  Actually, flow keeps language moving along and honest; it provides the reason for our awakening to changes in our world; it is of the very nature of life itself.  (With the terms in parentheses I allude to the problem, evoked above, of our dogmatically taking objects, acts, and events as generalities without due awareness of our so taking them because we are caught up in preconceptions, presuppositions, and prejudices, and can’t see our way into the middle road where alternatives can be found:  we must always be aware of our generalities and take them and make them judiciously.)

       If everything is always in a process of change, then we must be part of the same process.  I would suggest that we can without great difficulty at least begin to experience the process within which we find ourselves.  Find a quiet place and sit, just sit, and concentrate, on nothing at all.  “That’s easier said than done,” somebody retorts.  Yes, I know, accustomed as we are to the daily hubbub and our compulsion to engage in incessant palaver.  But try it.  Am I advocating Eastern meditation?  In a manner of speaking, yes.  It appears to be like those Eastern exercises that require much time and more patience, which most likely neither you nor I have at this time and place.  Nevertheless, just try it.  For a while, or preferably, as long as you can.  O.K.?  Now concentrate on what you have always done during every minute of your life but hardly ever thought about, if at all.  Concentrate on your lung heaves, the weight of your body on whatever is holding it up—of course I didn’t give you any instruction on what to sit on and how to sit, just sit.  Concentrate on your heartbeat.

Heartbeat, did I say?  Yes, heartbeat.  I happen to run a lot, at any time of the day, even to and from classes, for health and for sanity—though some of my associates think I’m a nut.  But for me, running’s where it’s at.  Because I am a running fanatic, my heartbeat is slow.  In fact, it’s very slow, perhaps too slow.  It is so slow that with each beat there must be quite a volume of blood taken in and put out.  When I am sitting still in a relatively quiet atmosphere I can feel the rhythm of every beat.  This is nothing out of the ordinary.  Everybody can become to a certain sense attuned to their body, or bodymind, to a considerably more profound degree than they think.  So, keep trying it, and I think you’ll see what I mean.  Just sit there for a while.  Then, slowly, concentrate on what your mind is doing when you try to keep it from doing anything at all.

Admittedly, what I wrote in the last sentence is a paradox if I ever heard one.  The mind keeping the mind from doing anything at all.  It’s like telling a baby not to suckle when an object touches its lips, like telling a cat not to stalk a ball of yarn rolling across the floor, like telling a squirrel to quit climbing trees.  The mind does what it does and there’s hardly anything we can do about it.  Nevertheless, just try it.  If you do it, diligently, I promise you you’ll come to an awareness of the incessant change that you would ordinarily take as no-change that is occurring in your body.  Sit and take in the feelings and sensations and experience for a while.

       Now put on a swimsuit and go jump in the nearest outside swimming pool on somewhat crisp late summer afternoon.  There are few swimmers around braving the cold water.  As soon as you jump in you let out a gasp result from the surprise your body felt.  Surprise your body felt?  What do I mean?  Just that.  Your body recorded the change in temperature and your brain registered the information and transformed it into a language you could understand.  Your mind does the act of becoming conscious of the change; your body is the vehicle that sends your mind the necessary information….

       But wait a minute.  You haven’t heard the whole story.  Stay in the pool for a few minutes.  Swim a few laps.  By the time you’re through, you’ll no longer feel the cold.  You’ll have become accustomed to it.  The water’s temperature is approximately the same; yet it no longer feels so cold.  Now you find you’re enjoying the water.  So you decide to take a few more laps, and then a few more.  It’s the same water, the same body, the same mind.  Yet they are all different.  The water is not the same as far as you’re concerned:  before, it was too cold, but now it is almost just right.  Your body is different.  It was previously in the air medium and rather comfortable, then in the cold water medium and uncomfortable, and finally, in the same water medium but feeling more at east.

Your mind has changed, but it did not do so in any autonomous fashion.  It co-participated with body and water environment and realized the change in interdependent, interaction interrelated with them.  It does nothing on its own.  In this sense bodymindworld is more appropriate, for they are never separated from one another, and if they were, there would be no life, no change, no language or any other mode of communication.  There would be no flow.  Bodymindworld fusion is essential to the process, the flow, change.  Life wouldn’t be worth living without the experience of change of bodymindworld.

       Of course this sort of knowledge was in the long lost past during the course of human evolution relegated to forgetfulness.  It has been forgotten, and we would most likely rather it stay in the past than come back to haunt us.  Why haunt us?  Because it is a silent, unwanted reminder of the world’s process, included us, within the interdependent, interrelated, interactive whole.  Since especially in Western thought, mind split off from body and world to create the illusion of its autonomy, its mastery of anything and everything.  As a consequence, mind naturally tends to flee from the reminder of what it is within the whole of bodymindworld.  Perhaps this forgetfulness, nevertheless, is essential in order that, after generations upon generations of unknowing transpired, knowing anew might be possible by way of remembering what was long ago forgotten.

At least that might be the hopeful wish, perhaps.


REFERENCES

 

 

Almeder, Robert (1980).  The Philosophy of Charles S. Peirce:  A Critical Introduction.  Totowa:  Rowman and Littlefield.

 

Barnes, B., D. Bloor and J. Henry (1996).  Scientific Knowledge:  A Sociological Analysis.  Chicago:  University of Chicago Press.

 

Bernstein, Richard J. (1983).  Beyond Objectivism and Relativism:  Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis.  Philadelphia:  University of Pennsylvania Press.

 

Bordo, Susan (1987).  The Flight to Objectivity:  Essays on Cartesianism and Culture.  Albany:  State Univeresity of New York Press.

 

Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari (1983).  Anti-Oedipus:  Capitalism and Schizophrenia I.  Minneapolis:  University of Minnesota Press.

 

Dozoretz, Jerry (1979).  “The Internally Real, the Fictitious, and the Indubitable.”  In Peirce Studies I, J. E. Brock, et al. (eds.), 77-87.  Lubbock:  Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism.

 

Emerson, Caryl (1997).  The First Hundred Years of Mikhail Bakhtin.  Princeton:  Princeton University Press.

 

Fisch, Max (1986).  Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism.  Bloomington:  Indiana University Press.

 

Fuller, Steve (1993).  Philosophy of Science and its Discontents.  New York:  Guilford Press.

 

Gleick, James (1987).  Chaos:  Making of a New Science.  New York:  Viking.

 

Goswami, Amit (1993).  The Self-Aware Universe.  New York:  J. P. Tarcher.

 

Haraway, Donna (1991).  Simians, Cyborgs, and Women:  The Reinvention of Nature.  New York:  Routledge.

 

Herbert, Nick (1985).  Quantum Reality:  Beyond the New Physics.  Garden City:  Anchor.

 

Hookway, Christopher (1985).  Peirce.  London:  Routledge and Kegan Paul.

 

Holton, Gerald (1970).  “Presupposition in the Construction of Theories.”  In Science and Literature, E. M. Jenning (ed.), 237-62.  Garden City:  Doubleday.

 

Koertge, Noretta (ed.) (1998).  A House Built on Sand:  Exposing Postmodern Myths about Science.  New York:  Oxford University Press.

 

Lovelock, John E. (1979).  Gaia, A New Look at Life on Earth.  Oxford:  Oxford University Press.

 

Margolis, Howard (1993).  Paradigms and Barriers:  How Habits of Mind Govern Scientific Beliefs.  Chicago:  University of Chicago Press.

 

merrell, floyd (1995).  Peirce’s Semiotics Now:  A Primer.  Toronto:  Canadian Scholars’ Press.

merrell, floyd (1997).  Peirce, Signs, and Meaning.  Toronto:  University of Toronto Press.

merrell, floyd (2000).  Signs for Everybody:  Or, Chaos, Quandaries, and Communication.  Ottawa:  Legas.

 

Peirce, Charles Sanders (1931-35).  Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1-6, C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss (eds.).  Cambridge:  Harvard University Press.

 

Polanyi, Michael (1958).  Personal Knowledge.  Chicago:  University of Chicago Press.

 

Prigogine, Ilya and Isabelle Stengers (1983).  Order Out of Chaos:  Man’s New Dialogue with Nature.  New York:  W. H. Freeman.

 

Saussure, Ferdinand de (1966).  Course in General Linguistics, trans. W. Baskin.  New York:  McGraw-Hill.

 

Whitehead, Alfred North (1925).  Science and the Modern World.  New York:  Macmillan.

 



[1]  In this light Gerald Holton (1970) discusses Newton’s suppressed fifth hypothesis that did not fit coherently with his four explicitly and forthrightly posited hypotheses; hence the reason for its suppression.

[2]  By the end of the nineteenth-century one of the most notable onlookers, it is becoming increasingly evident, was philosopher and semiotician and general polymath, Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914).  Peirce argued that we have no Cartesian power of infallible introspection or intuition.  In fact, there is no absolute guarantee that any given individual, however specialized s/he may be (especially in the post-Peirce sense), possesses the inside track to knowledge over anybody else (Einstein, for example, who as a child didn’t learn to speak until after his parents worried that he was retarded, as an adult was working in a patent office completely outside the mainstream of thought regarding matters of physical science).  Neither are we necessarily on the right track if we mindlessly take what authority hands down (1931-35 CP:5.264-65).  The best road, however fallible it might remain, lies within an entire interrelated, interacting, mutually cooperating and collaborating community of knowers.  In this vein, Peirce concludes:

The real, then, is that which, sooner or later, information and reasoning would finally result in, and which is therefore independent of the vagaries of you and me.  Thus, the very origin of the conception of reality shows that this conception involves the notion of an unlimited COMMUNITY, without definite limits and capable of a definite increase of knowledge. (CP:5.311)

            To put Peirce’s thought in a nutshell, if the real is “independent of the vagaries of you and me,” and if the most adequate method for knowing, however incompletely, this real, is by means of an “unlimited COMMUNITY,” then we cannot hope completely to know the real short of our belonging to an infinite community or a community that will be extended into the infinite future.  Finite and fallible knowers that we are, this infinite stretch where the grand epistemological pot of gold lies in eternal wait, is always beyond our reach (for further, Almeder 1980, Fisch 1986, Hookway 1985, merrell 1997).

[3]  While I can neither nor later give a viable account of “objective idealism” in this brief volume, I might suggest (Hookway 1985, merrell 1997).

[4]  Regarding the interrelations between the “real,” the imaginary or fictitious, and the “irreal” in the sense of Peirce, I know of no better source than an essay by Jerry Dozoretz (1979).

[5]  For an introduction to Peirce’s thought, see Almeder (1980); for a survey of his theory of the sign, I might venture to suggest merrell (1995, 2000).

[6]  Formulation of the becoming of things in this manner owes a debt to Deleuze and Guattari (1983).